andrew-bacon

PHIL 451: Exercises

Exercises 1

Let $P$ be God exists. Consider the argument

  1. $\Box (P \to \Box P)$ (Premise)

  2. $\Diamond P$ (Premise)

  3. $\Diamond \Box P$

  4. $P$

Given the possible worlds semantics, does the step from 1 and 2 to 3 seem to be good? What about the step from 3 to 4?

Draw a possible worlds diagram in which the inference fails: in which there is a world where 1 and 2 are true, and 4 is false.

Exercise 2

  1. Draw all the models over the frame $W=\{w,v\}$, $R=\{(w,v)\}$ in which every letter is false at every world, except $P$ (which can be true or false at any world). (There should be four.)

  2. Prove that $\{x \mid x\subseteq \{1\}\} = \{\{\}, \{1\}\}$.

  3. Suppose that we define $(a,b)$ as $\{\{a\}, \{a,b\}\}$. Prove that this definition satisfies the pairing principle: $(a,b)=(c,d)$ iff $a=c$ and $b=d$.

  4. Draw a frame with at least three worlds, and at least three arrows. Represent it as a set $W$ and a relation $R$ using set theoretic notation.

  5. Draw the frame with worlds $W=\{w, u, v\}$ and accessibility relation $R=\{(w,u), (u,v), (v,v), (w,w)\}$.

Exercise 3

  1. Consider the language $\mathcal{L}(\neg, \wedge)$. Define, by recursion, a function $v:\mathcal{L}(\neg, \wedge) \to \{0,1\}$ that

    (i) “makes the sentence letters true”: v(P)=1 for each letter P

    (ii) is a valuation valuation for this language: $v(\neg A) = 1-v(A)$ and $v(A\wedge B) = \min (v(A), v(B))$.

  2. Prove by induction that the function you defined in question 1 is indeed a valuation.

  3. Suppose that $v$ and $u$ are valuations for this language, and that for every letter, $P$, $v(P)=u(P)$. Prove by induction that $v=u$: that is for every sentence $A$, $v(A)=u(A)$.

  4. Given a Kripke frame, $(W,R)$, a valuation for the modal language $\mathcal{L}(\neg, \wedge, \Box)$ is a function $v:\mathcal{L}\times W \to \{0,1\}$ such that

    (i) $v(A\wedge B, w) = \min(v(A,w),v(B,w))$

    (ii) $v(\neg A, w) = 1-v(A,w)$

    (iii) $v(\Box A, w) = \min_{Rwv} v(A, v)$ (it is 1 iff $v(A,v)=1$ for all $v$ accessible to $w$).

intuitively $v(A,w)$ is the truth value of the sentence $A$ at the possible world $w$. Drawing on the ideas above, show how you would define a valuation on the modal language language in the Kripke frame $(W,R)$ by recursion.

Exercise 4

  1. Prove that $\Gamma \models A$ if and only if $\Gamma \cup \{\neg A\}$ is unsatisfiable.

  2. Show that any instance of the axiom A2 is valid.

  3. Show that $\{A\to B, A\}\models B$

  4. Prove by induction on proofs that if $\Gamma \vdash A$ then $\Gamma \models A$.

  5. Show that $\{(A\to B), (B\to C)\}\vdash (A\to C)$, i.e. find a derivation of the formula $(A\to C)$ from the assumptions $(A\to B), (B\to C)$.

Exercise 5

Suppose that the sentences of $\mathcal{L}(\neg,\to)$ have been enumerated $A_1, A_2, A_3,\ldots$, and suppose that $\Gamma$ is a consistent set of sentences. Let us define a sequence of extensions of $\Gamma$ as follows[^1]:

In this question you will show that $\Sigma$ is maximal consistent. In 1 and 2 you’ll show that it is consistent. In 4 you’ll show that it is maximal– this means that if $\Sigma, A$ is consistent then $A\in \Sigma$.

  1. Prove by induction on $n$ that $\Sigma_n$ is consistent for every number $n$.

  2. Prove that if $\Sigma$ is inconsistent, then $\Sigma_n$ is inconsistent for some $n$. Thus conclude that $\Sigma$ is consistent.

  3. Show that if $\Sigma, A$ is consistent then $A\in \Sigma$. (Hint: first show that if $\Sigma, A$ is consistent, then $\Sigma_n, A$ is consistent for any $n$, and use the fact that $A$ appears somewhere in our enumeration.)

  4. Using proposition 3.7 in the notes, show how to construct a valuation for any consistent set of sentences $\Gamma$.

[^1] Note that this is slightly simpler than my definition of $\Sigma_n$. Thanks to Arthur for noting that this works too!

Exercise 6

  1. A frame $(W,R)$ is reflexive iff $Rxx$ for all $x\in W$

    (i) Show that if a frame $(W,R)$ is reflexive (i.e. $Rww$ for every $w\in W$) then $\Box P \to P$ is valid in that frame.

    (ii) Show that if $\Box P \to P$ is valid in a frame, $(W,R)$, then $R$ is reflexive.

  2. A frame $(W,R)$ is symmetric iff $Rxy$ implies $Ryx$ for all $x,y\in W$

    (i) Show that if a frame $(W,R)$ is symmetric then $P \to \Box \Diamond P$ is valid in that frame.

    (ii) Show that if $P \to \Box \Diamond P$ is valid in a frame, $(W,R)$, then $R$ is symmetric.

  3. A frame $(W,R)$ is convergent iff, for any $x,y,y’\in W$, if $Rxy$ and $Rxy’$ then there exists a $z\in W$ such that $Ryz$ and $Ryz’$.

    (i) Show that if a frame $(W,R)$ is convergent then $\Diamond \Box P \to \Box \Diamond P$ is valid in that frame.

    (ii) Show that if $\Diamond \Box P \to \Box \Diamond P$ is valid in a frame, $(W,R)$, then $R$ is convergent.

Exercise 7

A formula $A$ characterizes a class of frames $\mathcal{C}$ when it contains all and only frames in which $A$ is valid.

  1. a. Show that a transitive reflexive frame satisfies the condition

    > Every world sees a "dead end" -- a world that only sees itself.
    

    if and only if $\Box\Diamond P \to \Diamond \Box P$ is valid.

    b. Find a single formula that characterizes transitive reflexive frames that satisfy this extra condition. (Hint: it could be a conjunction.)

  2. Find a formula that characterizes the class of frames with the property

    If $x$ sees $y$ then $y$ sees a world that sees $x$

Exercise 8

In this exercise you will show that the formula $\mathsf{L}$: $\Box(\Box P\to P) \to \Box P$ is valid only in frames that are transitive and are converse well-founded (there are no infinite sequences $x_1, x_2, x_3, …$ where $Rx_ix_{i+1}$ for all $i$.

  1. Suppose that $(W,R)$ is a frame in which $\mathsf{L}$ is valid. You will show that it is transitive and converse well-founded.

    a. Suppose, for contradiction, that $Rxy$ and $Ryz$ but not $Rxz$. Consider the valuation $V(P) = W\setminus\{y,z\}$. Show that (i) every world $x$ sees satisfies $\Box P\to P$, (ii) $x$ doesn’t make $\Box P$ true, to obtain a contradiction given the validity of $\mathsf{L}$.

    b. Suppose, for contradiction, that $x_1,x_2,x_3\ldots$ is a sequence with $Rx_ix_{i+1}$ and let $V(P)=W\setminus \{x_1, x_2,x_3,\ldots\}$. Using the fact that $R$ is transitive, show that for each $n$, (i) $x_n\Vdash \neg \Box P$, (ii) $x_n \Vdash \Box P \to P$, (iii) $x_n\Vdash (Box (\Box P\to P)$. Conclude that $R$ must be converse well-founded after all.

In the next exercise you will show that the property of being irreflexive (no world sees itself) is not frame definable.

  1. Consider the irreflexive frame $\mathcal{F} = (\{x,y\}, \{(x,y),(y,x)\}$ and the reflexive frame $\mathcal{G}=(\{w\}, \{(w,w)\}$. Given a valuation $V$ on $\mathcal{G}$ define a valuation $V’$ on $\mathcal{F}$ by $V’(P)=\{x,y\}$ if $V(P)=\{w\}$ and $V’(P)=\emptyset$ if $V(P)=\emptyset$.

    a. Prove by induction on formulas that that for any valuation $V$ with correspondingl defined $V’$, $x$, $y$ and $w$ make the same formulas true ($w$ with respect to $V$, $x$ and $y$ with respect to $V’$.

    b. Suppose, for contradiction, that $A$ is a formula that defines being irreflexive. Then $A$ should be valid on $\mathcal{F}$ but not $\mathcal{G}$. Explain why this is a contradiction.

Exercise 9

For these exercises you may assume the canonical model theorem: if $A$ is consistent in a modal logic $\Delta$ then $A$ is true at some world of the canonical model for $\Delta$.

  1. Show the completeness of $\mathsf{K4}$ ($\Box P\to \Box\Box P$) with respect to the class of transitive frames: if $A$ is consistent in $\mathsf{K4}$, then $A$ is satisfiable on some transitive frame (i.e. is true at some world in some model based on a transitive frame).

  2. Show the completeness of $\mathsf{KB}$ ($P\to \Box\Diamond P)$) with respect to the class of symmetric frames.

  3. Show that $\mathsf{S5}$ is complete with respect to the class of equivalence relations (transitive, reflexive, symmetric relations).

Exercise 10

$\mathsf{Alt}_n$ is the claim

$\Box P_1 \vee \Box(P_1\to P_2) \vee \Box (P_1\wedge P_2 \to P_3) \vee \ldots \vee \Box (P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_n \to P_{n+1})$

  1. Suppose every world in a frame sees at most $n$ worlds. Explain why $\mathsf{Alt}_n$ must be valid.

  2. Consider a frame in which some world sees $n+1$ or more worlds. Show that there is some valuation on this frame that invalidates $\mathsf{Alt}_n$.

Applications of Modal Logic: Reading

Metaphysical Necessity

Nathan Salmon. The Logic of What Might Have Been

Supplementary material: chapter 7 of Dorr, Hawthorne and Yli-Vakkury The Bounds of Possibility.

Vagueness

Andrew Bacon: Vagueness at Every Order

Supplementary material: Susanne Bobzien Columnar Higher-Order Vagueness, or Vagueness is Higher-Order Vagueness

Tense

Dorr and Goodman: Diamonds are Forever

Supplementary material: Arthur Prior Changes in Events and Changes in Things

Epistemic logic

Williamson Gettier Cases in Epistemic Logic

Stalnaker On Logics of Knowledge and Belief